8.1 Signaling concern for effectiveness/impact versus other values
Includes, e.g.,
social perceptions and ‘signaling empathy vs effectiveness’ ((Caviola, Schubert, and Nemirow 2020))
difficulty of coordinated signaling with a hard-to-coordinate measure such as ‘effectiveness’ Burum, Nowak, and Hoffman (2020)
Connection to terms/concepts in other work
- Caviola, Schubert, and Nemirow (2020) (literature review): Motivational obstacles, ‘Character and reputational benefit’.
8.2 Theory and argument
Simler and Hanson (2017) argue that social signaling is a major driver of human behavior, particularly in the charitable domain. Essentially, we may make choices that we would not have otherwise made in order to boost our reputation among our peers, colleagues, etc.. Reputation may be valued for its own sake or instrumentally, as a means to inducing others to act more favorably to us. Game theory (see esp. (Spence 1973)) offers a precise conception of this signaling as a costly way to demonstrate one’s positive “type” in a context with asymmetric information.
Several authors (can be interpreted to) suggest that valuing ‘’effectiveness in generosity’‘, i.e., moral-utilitarianism, is seen as a negative signal by peers and lowers fitness in the cooperation market, at least in comparison to signaling other empathic pro-social responses, perhaps involving a ’virtue ethic’. The exchange below captures the basic argument… (unfold)
(J. A. Everett, Pizarro, and Crockett 2016) argue that deontological ethics signal stable cooperative behavior to others, which enhances fitness in mutualistic partner choice models.1 The basic argument is “An individual who claims [and believes] that stealing is always morally wrong … seems much less likely to steal from me than an individual who believes that the stealing is sometimes morally acceptable depending on the consequences.”
Background and further discussion … in fold
Hoffman, Yoeli, and Nowak (2015) present an evolutionary game theoretic analysis of an indefinitely repeated game where2
- Player 1 can publicly ‘look’ to see the cost of cooperation,
- Player 1 next chooses to cooperate or defect, and then
- Player 2 chooses whether to continue repeating the above game, or end the relationship.
They provide conditions under which ‘cooperating without looking’ (CWOL) is part of a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, and an evolutionarily stable equilibrium can involve a substantial rate of CWOL play.
However, the analogy to effective versus ineffective giving is not clear. Perhaps a connection could be made if considering the charity effectiveness tended to provide a motivation to give less, but this is not obviously the case. In general, an ‘excuse not to do something’ is not the same as a ‘choice to be effective’.
8.3 Evidence for this barrier
We consider specific empirical claims that could be interpreted as evidence that this is an important barrier.
Evidence that “consequentialist choices lead to negative signals and less-favorable treatment relative to deontological/emotionally intuitive choices”
Although altruism is generally rewarded, several studies suggest that effective altruism is not
Citing: Burum et al, 2020; Montealegre et al, 2020; Yudkin et al, 2019
(J. A. Everett, Pizarro, and Crockett 2016)
J. A. Everett, Pizarro, and Crockett (2016) ran a series of experiments on the Mturk platform, involving hypothetical dilemmas paired with low-stakes (or no) Trust games.
In each, participants were asked to make and justify their judgement in a moral dilemma such as the famous ‘trolley dillemma’. In each case, this was a (hypothetical) choice between inaction and taking an action that sacrifices a small number of lives to save a larger number of lives.3
We then had our participants rate the morality and trustworthiness of each agent on a scale (Study 1a), play a hypothetical trust game (TG) with the agents (Study 1b), and, finally, play a TG involving real monetary stakes with the agents (Study
Across several studies deontologist agents were preferred in partner choices by participants endorsing the same values; even moral-utilitarians seem to favor peers who express emotional empathy and deontological ethics (ibid., p. 45).
However, this difference was not present in the track-switching dilemma, the only dilemma in which a majority favored the consequentialist choice.
Incorporate some of the other papers mentioned in the Gdoc here
Montealegre et al. (2020) Does Maximizing Good Make People Look Bad? Manuscript
Type of evidence: Online experiment (M-turk) with hypothetical choices (attitudes), six pre-registered studies using two different scenarios (N = 1,961)
Relation to charitable giving: directly, since …
Scenarios (including within and between subjects approaches):
- participants evaluate a response to survey question about how to select a charity (“If you were to donate, how would you select which charity to donate to?”).
Deliberative: I would use evidence to calculate which charity spends its donations most cost effectively, and donate to them.
Empathic: I would try to put myself in the shoes of people who are going through difficult situations, and donate to a charity that helped them.
- John was approached by a charity fundraiser and was asked whether he would be interested in donating to help Rokia, a 7-year-old girl from Mali, Africa who was desperately poor and faced the threat of severe hunger or even starvation. The charity fundraiser showed John a picture of Rokia (also presented to participants) and then asked John whether he would be interested in supporting her.
Across conditions, participants were presented with the general scenario and only the potential donor’s actions differed depending on the condition:
Deliberation: “John thought that donating to help Rokia might not be the most cost-effective way to use his money and that maybe he should donate to a charity doing something more cost-effective instead. He asked the charity fundraiser about the relevant statistics of the program and since the data suggested this charity was the most cost-effective John donated to the charity.”
Empathy: “John was deeply moved by Rokia’s situation and about how terrible her situation must be for her. After hearing about her tragic story and imagining how his donation could help her John donated to the charity.”
Robustness checks for: gender, stake size
Background mechanism: donors’ failure to prioritize cost-effectiveness can be explained by signaling concerns, since people who favor deontological over consequentialist decisions are preferred as social partners (J. A. C. Everett, Pizarro, and Crockett 2016)
Key findings: Across six studies, donors who deliberated were perceived as having worse moral character, were rated as less desirable as social partners, and were judged to be less guided by moral motives. On the other hand, those who deliberated were also seen as more reasonable and competent, and were judged to be more guided by pragmatic motives. Thus, there may be reputational benefits associated with deliberating. However, since deliberators are less preferred as social partners the authors believe the overall effect one reputation is negative. They do not find any differences in trustworthiness. Exhibiting empathy before deliberating reduced most negative reputational effects. People how do not give at all are seen as the worst. Surprisingly, participants judge the empathy donors as more wasteful.
Burum et al, ’20
(Burum, Nowak, and Hoffman 2020)
Involving variation in donation multipliers and social signaling/rewards4
Also
Yudkin et al, 2019, “Actions speak louder than outcomes in judgments of prosocial behavior”
Johnson https://psyarxiv.com/r85jv/ … Mturk experiments, people asked about praiseworthiness of hypothetical donors, between subject variation in amount donated and amount of impact achieved (1 of 6 studies)
Kawumara et al, 2020, perhaps in contrast to the above, seems to suggest that ‘effectiveness’ is rewarded with reputation. he people in the vignettes did seem to be rewarded (assessed as having both higher warmth and competence) by the participants for achieving a greater benefit, holding cost constant
Considerations
Even if we accept the above evidence (that those who make consequentialist active choices in “sacrificial dilemmas” are seen as less trustworthy and less moral) this may not generalize to effective giving. Researching and selecting a more effective charity is closest to the ‘track switching’ scenario in these experiments, in which no substantial difference was observed, and even here it is a stretch. Choosing a more effective charity instead of a more local one (e.g., river blindess prevention in Africa versus local guide Dogs) would be hard to cast seen as taking an active step to harm someone.5
Indirect evidence
(Kahane et al. (2018); Jordan et al. (2016); Hoffman, Yoeli, and Nowak (2015))
Jason Schukraft: I think the consequentialism vs deontology framing is a bit misleading. I think there’s an implicit virtue ethics at work here. Volunteering at the soup kitchen demonstrates the possession of certain virtues, and these virtues can’t be adequately signalled by donating to effective charities. (Donating to effective charities evidences other virtues, of course.)↩︎
Here the analogy to effective versus ineffective giving is not clear…↩︎
Would you “push a man off a footbridge to stop an oncoming train from hitting five”?↩︎
Writeup needed here↩︎
True, a local blind person may fail to get an additional (fraction of a) dog as a result of this choice. However, there is little sense in which “you funding his dog” would be seen as the status quo absent your intervention.↩︎